Search (2 results, page 1 of 1)

  • × author_ss:"Hersh, R."
  1. Davis, P.J.; Hersh, R.: Descartes' Traum : über die Mathematisierung von Zeit und Raum ; von denkenden Computern, Politik und Liebe (1988) 0.00
    0.002897586 = product of:
      0.033322237 = sum of:
        0.022674628 = weight(_text_:und in 3941) [ClassicSimilarity], result of:
          0.022674628 = score(doc=3941,freq=24.0), product of:
            0.053460475 = queryWeight, product of:
              2.216367 = idf(docFreq=13101, maxDocs=44218)
              0.024120769 = queryNorm
            0.42413816 = fieldWeight in 3941, product of:
              4.8989797 = tf(freq=24.0), with freq of:
                24.0 = termFreq=24.0
              2.216367 = idf(docFreq=13101, maxDocs=44218)
              0.0390625 = fieldNorm(doc=3941)
        0.01064761 = weight(_text_:im in 3941) [ClassicSimilarity], result of:
          0.01064761 = score(doc=3941,freq=2.0), product of:
            0.06818426 = queryWeight, product of:
              2.8267863 = idf(docFreq=7115, maxDocs=44218)
              0.024120769 = queryNorm
            0.15615936 = fieldWeight in 3941, product of:
              1.4142135 = tf(freq=2.0), with freq of:
                2.0 = termFreq=2.0
              2.8267863 = idf(docFreq=7115, maxDocs=44218)
              0.0390625 = fieldNorm(doc=3941)
      0.08695652 = coord(2/23)
    
    Abstract
    Es war René Descartes, der die Welt im 17. Jahrhundert auf den Kurs steuerte, dessen Stationen bald seine kühnsten Träume übersteigen sollten: die Rationalisierung der Welt, ihre Erkundung und Beherrschung durch die Methoden der Messung, des Zählens, Quantifizierens und Analysierens. Philip J. Davis und Reuben Hersh fahren diese Route erneut ab und stellen in ihrem »Kursbuch«, das erstmals 1986 erschien, eine Reihe wichtiger Fragen: Wie beeinflußt die Computerisierung der Welt die materiellen und intellektuellen Bausteine unserer Zivilisation? Wie verändert der Computer unsere Vorstellungen von der Realität, vom Wissen und von der Zeit? Hat er unser alltägliches Leben tatsächlich erleichtert?
    BK
    31.02 Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie der Mathematik
    54.08 Informatik in Beziehung zu Mensch und Gesellschaft
    Classification
    31.02 Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie der Mathematik
    54.08 Informatik in Beziehung zu Mensch und Gesellschaft
  2. Hersh, R.: Reply to Martin Gardner (2001) 0.00
    1.3680308E-4 = product of:
      0.0031464708 = sum of:
        0.0031464708 = product of:
          0.0062929415 = sum of:
            0.0062929415 = weight(_text_:1 in 3571) [ClassicSimilarity], result of:
              0.0062929415 = score(doc=3571,freq=10.0), product of:
                0.05925273 = queryWeight, product of:
                  2.4565027 = idf(docFreq=10304, maxDocs=44218)
                  0.024120769 = queryNorm
                0.10620509 = fieldWeight in 3571, product of:
                  3.1622777 = tf(freq=10.0), with freq of:
                    10.0 = termFreq=10.0
                  2.4565027 = idf(docFreq=10304, maxDocs=44218)
                  0.013671875 = fieldNorm(doc=3571)
          0.5 = coord(1/2)
      0.04347826 = coord(1/23)
    
    Content
    "Dear Martin Gardner, Thanks for your interest in my writings. As everyone knows, you're the most highly respected science journalist in the world. I just counted six of your books on my shelf. Yet for interesting, mysterious reasons, you seem unable or unwilling to understand my writing about mathematical existence. Your unhappiness with me is not new. You dissed The Mathematical Experience [1] by me and Phil Davis, in the New York Review of Books. In the most recent issue of The Intelligencer [4], you return to the task. You quote "myths 2, 3 and I from my Eureka article (reprinted in What is Mathematics, Really? [5], pp. 37-39). Myth 3 is somewhat off the point; I will concentrate on 2 and 4. Myth 4 is objectivity. "Mathematical truth or knowledge is the same for everyone. It does not depend on who in particular discovers it; in fact, it is true whether or not anyone discovers it." Your reaction: "What a strange contention" - to call it a myth. Myth 2 is certainty. "Mathematics possesses a method called 'proof' ... by which one attains absolute certainty of the conclusions, given the truth of the premises." Your reaction: "Can Hersh be serious when he calls this a myth'?" In a way, I understand your difficulty. In common speech, when someone says, "That's just a myth!" he means something is false, untrue. But in scholarly writing, "myth" commonly has other meanings. I wrote, on the very next page, "Being a myth doesn't entail its truth or falsity. Myths validate and support institutions; their truth may not be determinable'' About certainty, I wrote: "We're certain 2 + 2 = 4, though we don't all mean the same thing by that equation. It's another matter to claim certainty for the theorems of contemporary mathematics. Many of these theorems have proofs that fill dozens of pages. They're usually built on top of other theorems, whose proofs weren't checked in detail by the mathematician who quotes them. The proofs of these theorems replace boring details with 'it is easily seen' and 'a calculation gives.' Many papers have several coauthors, no one of whom thoroughly checked the whole paper. They may use machine calculations that none of the authors completely understands. A mathematician's confidence in some theorem need not mean she knows every step from the axioms of set theory up to the theorem she's interested in. It may include confidence in fellow researchers, journals, and referees.
    You go on: "I am an unabashed realist (for emotional reasons.) ... if all men vanished, there would still be a sense (exactly what sense is another and more difficult problem) in which spiral nebulae could be said to be spiral, and hexagonal ice crystals to be hexagonal, even though no human creatures were around to give these forms a name." "Exactly what sense" is exactly the issue! Leaving it at that is on a par with your "out there, never mind where." I turn to The Ways of a Philosophical Scrivener [3]. This book is a confession of faith. It is eloquent, touching, and immensely learned. I was impressed by the chapters "Faith: Why I am not an atheist" and "Immortality: Why I am not resigned." Starting on page 213, you write: "That the leap of faith springs from passionate hope and longing, or, to say the same thing, from passionate despair and fear, is readily admitted by most fideists, certainly by me and by the fideists I admire. ... Faith is the expression of feeling, of emotion, riot of reason ... How can a fideist admit that faith is a kind of madness, a dream fed by passionate desire, and yet maintain that one is not mad to make the leap? ... To believe what we do not know, what we hope for but cannot see-this is the very essence of faith. ... To believe in spite of anything! This is the essence of quixotic fideism ... With hope travels faith and with faith travels belief. But because it is belief of the heart backed by no evidence, it is never free of doubt. ..." After reading this, 1 finally appreciate your bitterly ironic quote from Swinburne. A self-named quixotic fideist has the hubris to tell me that saying man is the creator of mathematics is the ultimate in hubris! I'm sorry, Martin. 1 never wanted to disturb anyone's hope, faith, and belief. I'm sorry. P.S. 1 intended to answer your New York Review of Books article in my book, but my editor persuaded me not to. Thanks for this chance to respond in The Intelligencer."
    Footnote
    Bezugnahme auf: Gardner, M.: Is mathematics "out there"? In: The Mathematical intelligencer 23(2000) no.1, S.7-8